Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Varieties of Temporalization: Disciplinary Tasks Related to Historical Time

Abstract

This article calls attention to the outstanding conceptual work related to time that the historical research and writing imply. The starting point is an overview of the disciplines dedicated to time studies in the recent theory of history: the metaphysics of natural time, the (classical and the new) metaphysics of historical time, the regimes of historicity, and the historiographical regimes. According to these disciplines, four varieties of temporalization, with which historians have been dealing currently, are categorized and discussed: the chronological-historical, the substantive, the quasi-substantive, and the historically-experienced temporalization (and its narrative representation). This categorial structure, specially the quasi-substantive temporalization, assigns epistemic unity to the so-called new metaphysics of time and allows the classification of time-based concepts which are instrumentalized by historians. In order to demonstrate the consistency of the categories that this article proposes, some concepts concerning Koselleck’s theory of time (nature-like patterns of repetition, diachronic-synchronic layers of time, contemporaneity of the noncontemporaneous) will be studied as cases that illustrate the way a theorist combines different temporalizations to conceive of a theory of historical time that deals with the treatment of the temporal experience and the writing of history which integrate historians’ practice.

Keywords:
Philosophy of history; Temporalities; Reinhart Koselleck

Theory of History and Time Studies: a Diagram

Fernand Braudel (1902-1985) asserted that what decisively distinguishes the practice of history as a discipline is the way historians handle timeframe, provided that “History is a dialectic of the time span” (BRAUDEL, 1982BRAUDEL, Fernand. On History. Translated by Sarah Matthews. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1982. , p. 69), la dialectique de la durée. Likewise, Reinhart Koselleck (1923-2006) claims: “history can only exist as a science if it develops a theory of historical times without which history loses itself in the unlimited as a query concerning everything” (KOSELLECK, 2000KOSELLECK, Reinhart. “ Über die Theoriebedürftigkeit der Geschichtswissenschaft ”. In: KOSELLECK, Reinhart; GADAMER, Hans-Georg. Zeitschichten: Studien zur Historik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2000. p. 298-316, p. 302). However, the idea that historiographical practices and the theory of history’s disciplinary autonomy rely upon the theory of times (SIMON, 2019aSIMON, Zoltán Boldizsár. The story of humanity and the challenge of posthumanity. History of the Human Sciences, s/l, v. 2, n. 32, p. 101-120, 2019a, 101-120, 2019a, https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695118779519 , 14/02/2022.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695118779519...
, p. 102) is broadly accepted but barely assumed as a subject matter. In effect, Lynn Hunt warns that “Historians do not generally examine many of their categories of time” (HUNT, 2008HUNT, Lynn Avery. Measuring Time, Making History. Budapest: Central European University Share Company, 2008. p. 144-159., p. 22). Even worse, many historians might understand that the “‘theory’ or ‘philosophy’ constitute unnecessary distractions from their ‘real work’” (ZAMMITO, 2009ZAMMITO, John. Historians and Philosophy of Historiography. In: TUCKER, Aviezer (ed.). A Companion to Philosophy of History and Historiography. Oxford: Blackwell, 2009. p. 63-84., p. 64).

This poor backdrop has been changing since time studies draw lately significant academic attention. As a recent bibliometric study shows, since the 2000s (BEVERNAGE et. al., 2019BEVERNAGE, Berber; ALMEIDA, Gisele I. de; DELANOTE, Broos; FROEYMAN, Anton; HUIJBERS, Patty; MIEROOP, Kenan Van de. Philosophy of History after 1945: a bibliometric study. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 53, n. 3, p. 406-436, 2019, 406-436, 2019, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12124 , 03/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12124...
), both historians (LORENZ, 2017LORENZ, Chris. The Times They are a-Changin on Time, Space and Periodization in History. In: CARRETERO, Mario; BERGER, Stefan Berger; GREVER, Maria Grever (ed.). Palgrave Handbook of Research in Historical Culture and Education. Londres: Palgrave Macmillan, 2017. p. 109-131. , p. 109) and theorists (GORMAN, 2013GORMAN, Jonathan. The Limits of Historiographical Choice in Temporal Distinctions. In: LOREN, Chris; BERBER; Bevernage (ed.). Breaking up Time: Negotiating the Borders between Present, Past and Future. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2013. p. 155-175., p. 156) are increasingly attracted by the revival of the “ontology (of time)” that toned down narrativism (LORENZ, 2011LORENZ, Chris. History and Theory. In: SCHNEIDER, Axel; WOOLF, Daniel (ed.). The Oxford History of Historical Writing: Historical Writing Since 1945, v. 5. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. p. 13-35., p. 25-26). However, the increasing attention of historians and theorists cannot transform this theoretical inquiry to the extent at which time is reified as a historical agent, as Ankersmit warned: “in current texts celebrating historical time, the suggestion often is that time, not things happening in time, does the real work” (ANKERSMIT, 2021, p. 55). Between the revival of the ontology of time and the harmful entification of time, time studies build an epistemic unity related to different theoretical positions.

Aiming at account for the “plurality of disciplinary viewpoints and contexts” (HELLERMA, 2020aHELLERMA, Juhan. Mapping Time: Analysis of Contemporary Theories of Historical Temporality. Tartu: University of Tartu Press, 2020a., p. 9) that the investigation of temporality encompasses as a subject matter in the recent theory of history, this article begins by proposing an overview of time studies in the recent theory of history by means of Figure 1:

Figure 1.
Diagram of Time Studies Related to the Theory of History.

Figure 1 is a diagram divided by four parallel lines that define the subjects of time studies related to the theory of history: a) natural time; b) historical time; c) experience of historical time; d) historical time as it is integrated by historiographical practices and represented in historical writing. In between lines a, b, c, and d, there are the 1, 2, 3, and 4 areas, which encompass the different subfields of the historical time studies:

  1. Metaphysics of natural time (DENG, 2018DENG, Natalja. Metaphysics of time. In: CRANE, Tim (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 2018. , p. 1): it is located above line a, and looms ahead as the ultimate, misty boundary whereupon both the historians’ disciplinary practices and the theoretical efforts concerning historical time meet natural time;

  2. Metaphysics of historical time (KLEINBERG, 2012KLEINBERG, Ethan. Introduction: The New Metaphysics of Time. History and Theory, Virtual Issue, Middletown, p. 1-7, 2012, 1EthanIntro-1509464921000.pdf (wiley.com) , 26/03/2019., p. 1-7): it is located between lines a and b, meeting natural time on the top, and the experiences of historical time at the bottom;

  3. Regimes of historicity (HARTOG, 2015HARTOG, François. Regimes of Historicity: Presentism and Experiences of Time. Translated by Saskya Brown. New York: Columbia University Press , 2015., p. 106): it is located between lines b and c, and involves modes that the experience of historical time might take;

  4. Historiographical regimes (HARTOG; LENCLUD, 1993HARTOG, François; LENCLUD, Gérard. Régimes d’historicité. In: DUTU, Alexandre; DODILLE, Norbert (ed.). L´état des lieux en sciences sociales. Paris: L’Hamartan, 1993. p. 26-27. , p. 26-27): it is located below line d, and stands not only for the handling of time by historiographical practices related to time (chronology, timetables, periodization, chronicle) but also for the representation of historical time in historical writing.

This article understands that all the areas assigned in figure 1 develop different varieties of temporalization related to the disciplinary tasks of history. As this article’s specific goal is to categorize temporalizations related to history as a discipline, we will observe the temporalization that each subfield of the historical time studies (areas 1, 2, 3, and 4 of the diagram) develops according to different theoretical procedures.

It will be seen in detail that the metaphysics of natural time temporalizes by means of natural time and, therefore, seeks plotting history upon a non-human timeframe. Reciprocally, the metaphysics of historical time temporalizes by detaching historical time from natural time. The regimes of historicity temporalize the experience of historical time according to its varieties (past-, present-, or future-centered). The historiographical regimes temporalize the experience historical time by means of the representation of historical time in the writing of history. These varieties of temporalization will be defined and discussed in sections 2, 3, and 4. After that, the article will show by means of some of Koselleck’s temporal-based concepts (nature-like patterns of repetition, diachronic-synchronic layers of time, contemporaneity of the noncontemporaneous) that a successful theory of historical time nowadays shall involve a combination of these different temporalizations as disciplinary and practical tasks. This will be done in sections 5 and 6.

To begin, it is important to ask: does the categorization of varieties of temporalization bring some theoretical and practical gain to history as a discipline?

G. Deleuze (1925-1995) said that the symptomatology brings an important historical lesson: “symptoms are named, renamed, regrouped in various ways” over time (DELEUZE, 1991DELEUZE, Gilles. Masochism: coldness and cruelty & Venus in Furs. New York: Zone Books, 1991., p. 15). For instance, when the symptoms of the disease related to women’s womb called ‘hysteria’ were decomposed and regrouped under the psychosomatic spectrum, the hysteria, a former womb desease, gained a new symptomatology and etiology, which in turn opened the way for psychoanalysis to arise. Similarly, this article article intends to detect and map an innovative disciplinary field, the new metaphysics of historical time as it proposes the category of the quasi-substantive temporalization, which rearranges concepts of time studies related to the theory of history. At the same time, the conceptual rearrangement that the new metaphysics of historical time provides resets the relationship with the concurrent disciplines: the metaphysics of natural time, the classical metaphysics of historical time, the regimes of historicity, and the historiographical regimes, and their respective temporalizations: the chronological-historical, the substantive, and the historically-experienced temporalization.

To take into consideration the quasi-substantive temporalization and the new metaphysics of historical time, we should understand, in the first place, how the metaphysics of natural time temporalizes history.

Metaphysics of Natural Time: The Chronological-Historical Temporalization

What people ordinarily say about the experience of time, temporal change, and the relationship among past, present, and future are the starting point of the metaphysics of natural time, which usually labels itself as the metaphysics of time only (OAKLANDER, 2014OAKLANDER, Nathan L. Debates in the Metaphysics of Time, New York/London: Bloomsbury , 2014., p. x-xiv; BOCCARDI, 2016BOCCARDI, Emiliano. Recent Trends in the Philosophy of Time: An Introduction to Time and Reality I. Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 39, n. 4, p. 5-34, 2016., P. 5-6). The general title of the discipline implies no consideration of historical time as a special temporality, so the theorists of natural time understand historical time according to the ordinary linguistic structure that humans use to express the experience of time. Consequently, anyone could verify the truth of a statement about past events if they conveniently place themselves from the point of view of the one who originally said it (DUMMETT, 2004DUMMETT, Michael. Metaphysics of Time. In: DUMMETT, Michael (ed.). Truth and the Past. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. p. 73-96. , p. 44), notwithstanding whether the experience is directly felt or not. For instance, any person in the same time zone looking out from the window on a sunny day could have experienced the sunrise yesterday. The same procedure applies to a historical event, for instance, the Battle of Hysiae (417 B.C.) during the Peloponnesian War that Thucydides, who actually fought in the war, described. Basically, anyone could verify the truth of a past event if they could prove the eyewitness’ report about the reported event.

Even though the metaphysicians of natural time agree that the linguistic structure stands for the experience of time, they split into two parties regarding the intervening role that consciousness might play in the perception of the dimensional experience of time: a) cosmological time and b) time as the human mind pereceives it (MEYER, 2016MEYER, Ulrich. Consciousness and the Present. In: DOLEV, Yuval; ROUBACH, Michael (ed.). Cosmological and Psychological Time. New York: Springer, 2016. p. 143-153. , p. 143-145; KING, 2000KING, Preston. Thinking Past a Problem: Essays on the History of Ideas. London: Frank Cass, 2000., p. 29-30). The metaphysics of natural time integrates these two positions to conceive the unification of the physical time with the human experience of time, that is, the union between mind-dependent, human time and mind-independent, physical time: “There is just one fundamental physical time which the brain developed…” (GRUBER; BLOCK; MONTEMAYOR, 2022GRUBER, R. P.; BLOCK, R. A.; MONTEMAYOR C, -. Physical Time Within Human Time. Frontiers in Psychology, s/l, v. 13, article n. 718505, p. 1-13, 2022, 1-13, 2022, https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.718505 , 25/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.71850...
, p. 1). That integration launches an operation that will be categorized, henceforth, as the chronological-historical temporalization that the metaphysics of natural time provides about historical time.

The conscious participants think from inside time, so that their temporal perception is mind-dependent. However, they are also able to think outside time, that is, one can exchange the perspectival view of time for a mind-independent view, and vice-versa, provided that “The view through the eyes of the participant includes the view sub specie aeternitatis as the invariant relation among the parts of time” (ISMAEL, 2016ISMAEL, Jenann. From Physical Time to Human Time. In: DOLEV, Yuval; ROUBACH, Michael (ed.). Cosmological and Psychological Time. London: Springer. 2016. p. 107-124. , p. 119).1 1 In the jargon of the metaphysics of time, this integration corresponds with the conciliation between A-theory and B-theory, which McTaggart, the founder of the metaphysics of time, considered thoroughly incompatible. In short, individuals can look at themselves from the outside as parts of a cosmological timeline that exceeds any embodied participant.

Eventually, the combination between physical-natural and conscious-human time, which the chronological-historical temporalization implies, is the superimposition between two chronological scales: the one uses a cosmological timeframe of which consciousness does not take part, and the other uses a human timeframe through which consciousness posits itself as an inside observer of their own displacement through a timeline.

Could historical time be conceived of as something more than a composition of chronological scales? This is the question that the metaphysics of historical time asks.

Metaphysics of Historical Time and Substantive Temporalization

While the metaphysics of natural time, as the previous account shows, seeks to bridge physical time and human time in order to propose a chronological-historical temporalization, the metaphysics of historical time admits the mutual and initial entanglement of both. In fact, it recognizes natural time as part of the historical experience. Nevertheless, the metaphysics of historical time emerges as a disciplinary field as it painstakingly strives to set natural and human time apart as a condition to think historically. It starts from the assumption that human time can mold its relationship with natural time to the extent at which nature becomes increasingly secondary to history. Eventually, nature remains as history’s ultimate boundary towards which historical time dissipates in the natural time.

For instance, according to Pomian, the order of time can take four timeframes, namely: “chronometry,” “chronology,” “chronography,” and “chronosophy” (POMIAN, 1984POMIAN, Krzysztof. L’Ordre du temps. Paris: Gallimard , 1984. , p. ix). These operations gradually put human time away from natural time until human time can be considered thoroughly historical time. The two first timeframes are related to the calendar and chronological time and superimpose human and natural time. Chronography, the third Pomian timeframe, pushes natural time further from human time by introducing an active subject that arranges the events in a chronicle so that the order of natural time merely becomes a temporal marker of the story told, no matter how extended (being the upper limit of the cosmological time) or contracted (being the lower limit of the instantaneous present) the chronological markers may be.

Chronosophy, the fourth timeframe in turn detaches history from natural time even further by placing nature as the temporal threshold from which the historical time arises and, at the same time, for historical time to claim its identity as the non-chronological human time relatively to chronological, physical, natural time. Chronosophies imply that history proceeds with time, but it does not find its characteristic in any chronological scale upon which both natural time and human time could be measured indistinctively. In fact, it sets an endogenous temporalization regarding historical events. Thus, the progressive detachment of human time from natural time reaches the highest level, as cultural and social events temporalize human time as historical time. This detachment remains undisputed since human and natural timescales do not mingle.

First of all, the historical time is not natural time, and the former must detach from the latter to be historical. From the threshold that separates historical and natural time, the metaphysics of historical time builds its own disciplinary framework. The separation of history from nature can take two basic positions. The first position involves Kant’s, Hegel’s, Marx’s, Nietzsche’s, and Heidegger’s classical philosophy of history, and the second the “new metaphysics of time” (KLEINBERG, 2012KLEINBERG, Ethan. Introduction: The New Metaphysics of Time. History and Theory, Virtual Issue, Middletown, p. 1-7, 2012, 1EthanIntro-1509464921000.pdf (wiley.com) , 26/03/2019., p. 1).

The classical metaphysics (philosophy) of historical time assumes a substantive temporalization. It is, in general, devoted to the Hegelian inquiry regarding the internal sense of historical time: Should history lead societies to a purposive and progressive direction despite the potential chaos of human actions in the present? Therefore, it “aspire[s] to understand once and for all [d’amblée] the entire course [...] of history, of becoming or of time” (POMIAN, 1984POMIAN, Krzysztof. L’Ordre du temps. Paris: Gallimard , 1984. , p. 5) by knowing in advance what the “relationship [rapports] between the present, the past and the future” (POMIAN, 1984POMIAN, Krzysztof. L’Ordre du temps. Paris: Gallimard , 1984. , p. vi) essentially means. In order to search for the all-encompassing sense of history, the classical philosophies of history demanded a stronger, totalizing, more than mere chronological meaning, for history to fully withdraw from nature. That is the substantive temporalization, which is a kind of temporalization that intends to unveil “the historical significance of history as a whole” (DANTO, 1985DANTO, Arthur C. Narration and knowledge. New York: Columbia University Press, 1985., p. 13).

The emergence of the new metaphysics of time is very recent in comparison with the centennial origins of the classical metaphysics of historical time. In fact, by the turn of the first decade of this century, the outline of this new field of time studies was still vague. In 2011, Jordheim pointed that the “theory of historical times [specially Koselleck’s] at present is both contested and simply overlooked” (JORDHEIM, 2011JORDHEIM, Helge. Does Conceptual History Really Need a Theory of Historical Times? Contributions to the History of Concepts, Oxford, v. 6, n. 2, p. 21-41, 2011, 21-41, 2011, https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202 , 24/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202...
, p. 21). In contrast, one year after this skeptical evaluation regarding time studies, Kleinberg indicated that a “new metaphysics of time” (KLEINBERG, 2012KLEINBERG, Ethan. Introduction: The New Metaphysics of Time. History and Theory, Virtual Issue, Middletown, p. 1-7, 2012, 1EthanIntro-1509464921000.pdf (wiley.com) , 26/03/2019., p. 1-2) had risen.

The difference between the classical and the new metaphysics of historical time involves a paradigmatic conflict that ruled the historical thinking for decades, which began with the rejection of the substantive temporalization.

The strongest reaction against the substantive temporalization dates from the 1960s when Arthur C. Danto (1924-2013) launched the thesis according to which there must be an analytical philosophy of history dedicated to the “conceptual problems which arise out of the practice of history as well as out of substantive philosophy of history” (DANTO, 1985aDANTO, Arthur C. Narration and knowledge. New York: Columbia University Press, 1985., p. xv). Danto refused the substantive philosophy of history due to the speculative risks that not only the philosophers of history but also theorists and professional historians might take, as they seek “to give an account of the whole of history” (DANTO, 1985bDELEUZE, Gilles. Masochism: coldness and cruelty & Venus in Furs. New York: Zone Books, 1991., p. 167-168). Consequently, they should restrain the theoretical enterprise instead to the temporal references that the historians’ language ordinarily uses to write the “narrative sentences” out of which historical knowledge is effectively made (DANTO, 1985bDELEUZE, Gilles. Masochism: coldness and cruelty & Venus in Furs. New York: Zone Books, 1991., p. 178-179).

The contention of the analytical philosophy of history against the substantive temporalization opened the way to the narrativist philosophy of history, from the 1980’on, and to a new type of temporalization that the new metaphysics of historical time launched from the 2000’s on, as we will see in the next section.

Temporalization in the Context of the Paradigmatic Conflict

The new metaphysics of historical time reconsiders the weight of the substantive characteristic of time for history. Therefore, it has to negotiate with the rejection of the substantive temporalization by the narrativist philosophy of history.

On the one hand, the new metaphysics of time did not forget Hayden White’s lesson according to which historians tell stories about events that are language-dependent, and that the historical writing is shaped by “poetic” cultural patterns of ordering historical narrative or “emplotment” (romance, tragedy, comedy, and satire) which are “metahistorical” (WHITE, 1975WHITE, Hayden. Metahistory: the historical imagination in nineteenth-century Europe. Maryland: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975. , p. ix). Decades of immersion in the Whitean narrativism immunized more recent theories of historical time against the speculative risks that the substantive philosophy of history took about conceiving the overall sense of history. It also made historians and theorists cautious about substantive temporalization as the underlying basis that historical language should conform to. In short, the new metaphysics of time could not dispense with the rejection to the substantive idea of historical time as a mind-independent experience that language represents.

On the other hand, if the new metaphysics of historical time takes part in that long-lasting contention against the substantive philosophies of history, it will not thoroughly reject them. In fact, the new metaphysics of historical time retrieves and renews some of the old substantive temporalizations, such as the representation of time regarding events and experienced history, concrete engagement among past, present, and future, temporal change, and continuity/discontinuity of historical time. According to Simon, the current phase of the theory of history does not exactly show a hard divide between the classical and the new metaphysics of historical time, but a movement along which new theories of historical time launch a “quasi-substantive philosophy of history” (SIMON, 2019bSIMON, Zóltan B. History in Times of Unprecedented Change: A Theory for the 21st Century. London: Bloomsbury , 2019b. , p. 39).

Accordingly, the new metaphysics of historical time assumes a quasi-substantive temporalization by combining the classical issues regarding the historical time and the suspicion that narrativism raised against the substantive philosophies of history. Even though indebted to White’s thesis, narrativism is not ontologically interested in historical time, whereas the new metaphysics of history approach is. The new metaphysics of historical time understands historical writing as the representation and interpretation of the historical experience, but it goes further as it contends narrativism’s tendency to reduce “the role played by time as a factor in the process of constituting historical forms” (HAROOTUNIAN, 2013HAROOTUNIAN, Harry. Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts: Hayden White and the Question of Temporal Form. In: DORAN, Robert (ed.). Philosophy of History After Hayden White. London: Bloomsbury, 2013. p. 119-149. , p. 120), so that time became a mere rhetorical construct - a “narrative’s time” (HAROOTUNIAN, 2013HAROOTUNIAN, Harry. Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts: Hayden White and the Question of Temporal Form. In: DORAN, Robert (ed.). Philosophy of History After Hayden White. London: Bloomsbury, 2013. p. 119-149. , p. 130).

At last, which ideas the new metaphysics of historical time provide to the historians’ disciplinary tasks that the classical, the narrativist, and the analytical philosophers of history could not? To answer this question, we shall define the parameters that structure the metaphysics of historical time: i. detachment of the historical time from the natural time, ii. relationship among past, present, and future, iii. temporal change.

i. The quasi-substantive temporalization does not deal with the detachment of the historical from natural time. In general, it temporalizes history as detached from natural time in the first place, in so far as historical knowledge responds to nature either by converting time into a human matter (RUSEN, 2013RUSEN, Jorn. Historik: Theorie der Geschichtswissenschaft. Kol/Weimar/Wein: Bohlau Verlag, 2013., p. 33) or by humanizing natural-like patterns as reverberations of nature in history (KOSELLECK, 2018KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018., p. 29). In fact, the new metaphysics of historical time at the start restrains itself to the disciplinary demands of history as it places it self against “a kind of thinking that overflows that of the knowable […] limits [within which] historians’ history confines itself” (RICOEUR, 2004RICOEUR, Paul. Memory, history, forgetting. Translated by Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004. , p. 155). At best, it considers natural time as a distant border that runs inconspicuously beneath the threshold of human time which from time to time might emerge with catastrophic and disruptive consequences that confront individuals and societies with the natural limits of their lives.

ii. and iii. The new theories of historical time consider that the relationship among past, present, and future changed its central issues. Therefore, the quasi-substantive temporalization emphasizes the diversity among those relationships, not aiming at revealing the sense of history as the secret of temporal passage, so that temporal change is a matter of involvement between the past and the present. For instance, historical change regarding the theories of presence is related to the effect that the presentification of the absent past has upon the present, since presence is the “fistula” that transfers the present of the past into the present as it connects two contiguous layers in the same location pushing time forward (RUNIA, 2006RUNIA, Eelco. “Presence”, History and Theory, Middletown, v. 45, n. 1, p. 1-29, 2006, 1-29, 2006, https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590722 , 15/02/2019.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590722...
, p. 10).

However, the quasi-substantive temporalization would remain only as an abstractive exercise, if the new metaphysics of historical time does not take into account the experience of historical time regarding the historically-experienced temporalization.

Culturally and socially experienced historical time fits the historians’ disciplinary needs. The historians describe historical events temporally lived, not concepts of time. In general, the affirmation of an experienced, ordinary historical time coincides with a movement that affirms the autonomy of history as a professional discipline and acknowledges the theory of history as its reflective meta-discipline. In effect, the substantive and speculative character of the classical philosophies of history have been firstly opposed by historians, for instance, by Leopold von Ranke’s (1795-1886) historicism (IGGERS, 2011IGGERS, George G. Introduction. In: IGGERS, Georg G (ed.). The Theory and Practice of History: Leopold von Ranke. London: Routledge , 2011. p. xi-xlv. , p. xxvi-xxvii), as early as the mid-nineteenth century. This reactive movement on the part of professional historians continued during the twentieth century, for instance, by the Annale’s icons Marc Bloch (BLOCH, 1953BLOCH, Marc. The Historian’s Craft. New York: Vintage Books, 1953., p. 3) and Jacques Le Goff (LE GOFF, 1988LE GOFF, Jacques. Histoire et mémoire. Paris: Gallimard, 1988. , p. 24), who rejected the philosophy of history.

The long-lasting contention of historians against the philosophies of history is supported by recognized theorists of history, such as Paul Ricoeur (1913-2005), Reinhart Koselleck (1923-2006), Hans U. Gumbrecht, Frank Ankersmit, and Paul A. Roth, who took part in the narrative turn and, at the same time, maintained historical time as a subject of inquiry. Moreover, the renowned works of those prolific theorists circulate since the two decades of the twentieth-first century and influenced theorists of historical time such as Achim Landwehr, Anton Froeyman, Berber Bevernage, Eelco Runia, Ethan Kleinberg, Hans U. Gumbrecht, Ewa Domanska, Helge Jordheim, Zoltán B. Simon, to cite a few.

The new metaphysics of historical time tunes the demands of the recent theories of historical time to the ontological demands of theorists of history - the quasi-substantive temporalization - and to the historians’ disciplinary tasks related to human time and change in history, that is, the experienced historical time. This effort, according to Hellerma, involves different theories of time that investigate the ontological conditions for possible relations between past, present, and future and “thus seek to establish conceptual ground valid and informative across concrete temporal attitudes and temporal regimes and chronotopes” (HELLERMA, 2020aHELLERMA, Juhan. Mapping Time: Analysis of Contemporary Theories of Historical Temporality. Tartu: University of Tartu Press, 2020a., p. 19). In short, the quasi-substantive and the historically-experienced temporalizations together give access to the regimes of historicity and historiographical regimes, as will be seen in the next sections by means of the analyses of Koselleck’s theory of time.

The Quasi-Substantive Temporalization and Koselleck’s Multiple Temporalities

Koselleck’s multiple temporalities will be characterized as a theory of time that combines three categories that the previous sections defined: the chronological-historical time, the quasi-substantive, and the historically-experienced temporalization. Firstly, we will show how some Koselleck’s concepts related to natural and historical time (nature-like patterns of repetition, diachronic-synchronic layers of time, contemporaneity of the noncontemporaneous) exemplify the reach and range of the proposed categorizations. Secondly, the combination of these categories provides disciplinary tools for historians to deal with the regimes of historicity that analyses the temporal experience and historiographical regimes by means of which experienced historical time is represented (see Figure 1).

Against the backdrop described in the previous sections, without a shadow of a doubt, Koselleck’s theory of historical time played a decisive role in placing “the issue of historical time on the agenda in German and international historiography” (OLSEN, 2013OLSEN, Niklas. History in the Plural: An introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck. New York: Berghahn Books, 2013. , p. 232), from the 1980’s on, when narrativism put aside ontological questions. To be precise, Koselleck faced the challenge about historical time: “The question of what historical time belongs to those questions which historical science has the most difficulty answering” (RICOEUR, 2004RICOEUR, Paul. Memory, history, forgetting. Translated by Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004. , p. xxi).

Therefore, among the theories of time that share the broad field of the metaphysics of historical time, what would definitively characterize Koselleck’s recognized theory about historical time?

For Kleinberg, the field of the new metaphysics of time acquired a steady basis and could be mapped into three emerging trends: “presence, multiple temporalities, and reconceptualizing history” (KLEINBERG, 2012KLEINBERG, Ethan. Introduction: The New Metaphysics of Time. History and Theory, Virtual Issue, Middletown, p. 1-7, 2012, 1EthanIntro-1509464921000.pdf (wiley.com) , 26/03/2019., p. 2). In effect, the second trend of the new metaphysics of time is properly named multiple temporalities after Koselleck’s influence over the field of time studies in the recent theory of history. To be precise, Koselleck’s theory of history paves the way for the development of the new metaphysics of historical time as it launches a quasi-substantive philosophy of history in terms of multitemporal relations. It overcomes the anti-speculative prejudice by bringing together history, as knowledge or narrative - therefore, an epistemological approach -, and the structure of the intertwined dimensions of time - therefore, an ontological appeal to historical experience (BOUTON, 2016BOUTON, Christophe. The Critical Theory of History: Rethinking the Philosophy of History in the Light of Koselleck’s Work. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 2, n. 55, p. 163-184, 2016, 163-184, 2016, https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668 , 29/04/2022.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668...
, p. 173-174). Likewise, according to Escudier, Koselleck’s theory of time stands out “both by [the] degree of philosophical formalization and by [its] heuristic empirical scope” (ESCUDIER, 2009ESCUDIER, Alexandre. “Temporalization” and Political Modernity: thinking with Koselleck. Annales: Histoire, Sciences Sociales, Paris, v. 64, n. 6, p. 1269-1301, 2009, 1269-1301, 2009, https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-2009-6-page-1269.htm , 23/09/2022.
https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-200...
, p. 1269). From the ontological point of view, the theory of multiple temporalities, basically, teaches historians and theorists of history to pay attention to the existence of not only “one historical time, but rather […] many forms of time superimposed one upon the other” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 2).

According to Ankersmit, “the notion of the layers of time has much in common with the notion of structure that was so popular among French and German historians in the 1970s and the 1980s” (ANKERSMIT, 2021, p. 44). In fact, even though the multilayered arrangement of historical times makes the soil of history restless, it is possible to detect “temporal structures” (KOSELLECK, 2018KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018., p. 94) which pulse regularly according to a lively temporal factor. In addition, the Koselleckian structure of time is closer to the Braudelian structural longue durée than to its structuralist and poststructuralist counterparts, as the diachronic structures “unfold not vertically, in the space of synchronic discourse, as for Saussure and Foucault, but horizontally, in diachronic time” (JORDHEIM, 2011JORDHEIM, Helge. Does Conceptual History Really Need a Theory of Historical Times? Contributions to the History of Concepts, Oxford, v. 6, n. 2, p. 21-41, 2011, 21-41, 2011, https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202 , 24/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202...
, p. 33).

To explain the design of the Koselleckian structure of time as the temporal, multilayered-arranged schemas (HELLERMA, 2020bHELLERMA, Juhan. Koselleck on Modernity, Historik, and Layers of Time. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 59, n. 2, p. 188-209, 2020b, 188-209, 2020b, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154 , 23/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154...
, p. 195), the parameters related to the quasi-substantive temporalization according to the previous section (i. detachment of the historical time from the natural time, ii. relationship among past, present, and future, iii. temporal change) will show to be developers of the Koselleckian metaphysics of historical time according to the following interrelated instances: i.1. the nature-like patterns of repetition of historical time, i.2. the multilayered, diachronic-synchronic arrangement of the relationship among past, present, and future, and i.3. the rhythm of temporal change in the instance of the “contemporaneity of the noncontemporaneous”. In short, i.1., 1.2., and i.3. together integrate and perform the Koselleckian quasi-substantive temporalization, as will be seen.

Firstly (i.1.), the Koselleckian temporal structures of history ultimately face natural time, even though they are “imbued with a strong, theoretically motivated, and methodologically implemented anthropocentrism.” (JORDHEIM, 2022JORDHEIM, Helge. Natural Histories for The Anthropocene: Koselleck’s Theories and The Possibility of a History of Lifetimes. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 61, n. 3, p. 391-425, 2022, 391-425, 2022, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268 , 30/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268...
, p. 396). In fact, not being insensitive to the role that natural time plays in historical thinking, Koselleck stated that history ought to be considered apart from the natural, clock time, since “historical time remains embedded within natural time without being entirely contained in it” (KOSELLECK, 2000KOSELLECK, Reinhart. “ Über die Theoriebedürftigkeit der Geschichtswissenschaft ”. In: KOSELLECK, Reinhart; GADAMER, Hans-Georg. Zeitschichten: Studien zur Historik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2000. p. 298-316, p. 304). Historical time relatively departs from natural time because interrelations of human events “forces us to adopt social and political determinations of time that, although they are naturally caused, must be defined as specifically historical” (KOSELLECK, 2002KOSELLECK, Reinhart. The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Translated by Todd Samuel, Kirstin Behnke and Jobst Welge. Stanford: Stanford University Press , 2002. , p. 110).

Humans can be considered apart from nature with regard to “historical interrelations” since the latter are not “entirely contained” in natural time. Despite their divorce, even historiography cannot dispense with natural time (KOSELLECK, 2002KOSELLECK, Reinhart. The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Translated by Todd Samuel, Kirstin Behnke and Jobst Welge. Stanford: Stanford University Press , 2002. , p. 106) since “social and political determinations” of history entail some resonances of nature. In effect, the structure of historical time, even though immersed in the human and institutional agency (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 2), instantiates itself by means of nature-like patterns of repetition, such as generational constraints, biological rhythms, cycles of life and death, and others, towards evolutionary, geographical, geological, and astrophysical time, all of them “pregivens of possible histories that escape human control but not human use” (KOSELLECK, 2018KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018., p. 29). Hence, the involvement of the Koselleckian temporal structures with natural time is translated by categories on the border between nature and history (OLSEN, 2013OLSEN, Niklas. History in the Plural: An introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck. New York: Berghahn Books, 2013. , p. 227). That is, the chronological-historical temporalization, as defined in the second section of this article, is a variety of temporalization which is adapted by Koselleck as the inner reverberation of the repetition that characterizes natural time inside historical time, on the condition that humans are on the top of these “structures of repetition” since only language can discover and recognize natural patterns of repetition (KOSELLECK, 2018KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018., p. 162-163).

Secondly (i.2.), Koselleck summarizes in a geological image his lesson about the relationship among past, present, and future, which mingles and merges in a changeable sheaf of “‘layers of time’ […] that differ in age and depth and that changed and set themselves apart from each other at differing speeds over the course of the so-called history of the earth” (KOSELLECK, 2018KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018., p. 3). The layered characteristic of a temporal structure avoids the realignment of both past and present as antecedent and subsequent in a linear timeline since any revolving layer of historical time is interdependent. The multilayered historical time beats in two combined rhythms. On the one side, there is the diachronic distance that separates the past from the present. On the other side, past and present are synchronic and contiguous as layered times. In short, the structure of historical time is diachronically and synchronically intertwined according to their dissonant rhythms of temporal change (KOSELLECK, 2002KOSELLECK, Reinhart. The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Translated by Todd Samuel, Kirstin Behnke and Jobst Welge. Stanford: Stanford University Press , 2002. , p. 30).

Thirdly (i.3.), and consequently, the order of historical time regarding the relationship among past, present, and future, locates temporal change in the “contemporaneity of the noncontemporaneous” (KOSELLECK, 2002KOSELLECK, Reinhart. The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Translated by Todd Samuel, Kirstin Behnke and Jobst Welge. Stanford: Stanford University Press , 2002. , p. 90), since the layered involvement of the past and the present unsettles any layer of time and makes the passage of time historically perceptible as a restless involvement between past and present both diachronically and synchronically.

The relationship between natural and historical time according to patterns of repetition, the layered diachronic-synchronic relationship among past, present, and future, and the historical change based on the dynamics of the contemporaneous over the noncontemporaneous characterize what Koselleck named temporal structures and summarize the Koselleckian quasi-substantive temporalization, according to the categorial work this article proposes.

Furthermore, the ‘contemporaneity of the noncontemporaneous’ allows the historical change to be felt in so far as it conveys a sense of experiencing historical time in terms of historical change. Consequently, the experienced historical time provides historians with a non-chronological, immanent procedure regarding the periodization of historical change to differentiate types of historical experience: “The past, then, may be, and often is, distinguished from the present not by reference to chronology (‘the passage of time’), but by reference to significant and substantive changes in behavior and activity” (KING, 2000KING, Preston. Thinking Past a Problem: Essays on the History of Ideas. London: Frank Cass, 2000., p. 45).

In effect, the involvement of the temporal layers in the temporal structures can be differently shaped according to the specific ranges of the experienced history they instantiate. The recursive structures of historical time, even though supporting a law-like, natural character, cannot be measured with a clock due to the mutual interference of multiple layers of time (KOSELLECK, 2000KOSELLECK, Reinhart. “ Über die Theoriebedürftigkeit der Geschichtswissenschaft ”. In: KOSELLECK, Reinhart; GADAMER, Hans-Georg. Zeitschichten: Studien zur Historik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2000. p. 298-316, p. 304). Therefore, those structures of repetition should be detected in the time passage as such, provided that the temporal structure and its shift over time are demonstrated by the unfolding experienced events that actualize and singularize them (OLSEN, 2013OLSEN, Niklas. History in the Plural: An introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck. New York: Berghahn Books, 2013. , p. 226). Structures of repetition such as cosmological and biological durations along with their expression in language, especially in concepts used to talk about history and historical time, must be detected by historians since they are “durable structures that continue to determine human existence” (ESPOSITO, 2021ESPOSITO, Fernando. Despite Singularity: The Event and its Manifold Structures of Repetition. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 60, n. 1, p. 86-101, 2021, 86-101, 2021, http://www.jstor.org/stable/27799186 , 31/03/2023.
http://www.jstor.org/stable/27799186...
, p. 97).

All in all, Koselleck’s quasi-substantive temporalization engages the ontological reflection on historical time with the historians’ disciplinary work, that is, it becomes feasible through the immanent discrimination of the periods that different temporal experiences might take over time (ZAMMITO, 2004ZAMMITO, John. Koselleck’s Philosophy of Historical Time(s) and the Practice of History. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 43, n. 1, p. 124-135, 2004, 124-135, 2004, https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590747 , 20/04/2023.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590747...
, p. 126). The quasi-substantive historical temporalization, therefore, besides establishing the metaphysical or ontological image of historical time as a multilayered temporal structure, shows that the latter can be historiographically worked out according to the historians’ epistemological task of periodizing and analyzing the varieties of the experienced historical time. In fact, according to Ankersmit (ANKERSMIT, 2021, p. 36), “the ‘inside’ ([historical] ontology) and the ‘outside’ ([historical] epistemology) are interwoven” in Koselleck’s works. Eventually, as Zammito assumes, “Koselleck’s theory of ‘sediments of time’ aims at the enablement of historical practice” (ZAMMITO, 2021ZAMMITO, John. Koselleck’s Times. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 60, n. 2, p. 396-405, 2021, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12215, 21/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12215, 21/0...
, p. 403).

At this point, despite the conceptual tools for the disciplinary practice that the Koselleckian of the multilayered historical time provide, it “ultimately does not describe any concrete experience of history” (HELLERMA, 2020aHELLERMA, Juhan. Mapping Time: Analysis of Contemporary Theories of Historical Temporality. Tartu: University of Tartu Press, 2020a., p. 17). Should a further step be made for the theory of time to reach the “concrete experience of history”?

Regimes of Historicity and Historiographical Regimes: Combining Temporalizations and Historicizing Historical Experience

According to the diagram of time studies in the recent theory of history (figure 1), the metaphysics of natural and of historical time, the regimes of historicity, and the historiographical regimes are situated in different areas. However, those areas are interrelated, and the representative authors of each area often go across the other areas. As a matter of fact, Koselleck’s theory of time irradiates up and downward from the metaphysics of historical time to consider natural time, regimes of historicity (historical experience) and historiographical regimes (representation of historical time), thereby combining different varieties of temporalization. Consequently, it is possible to follow in detail the development of the Koselleckian metaphysics of historical time as it spreads all over the disciplines related to time studies and meets the point of convergence of the historians’ disciplinary tasks. The Koselleckian theory of time allows to understand how historical time arises and leaves natural time, relates historical time to historical experience, and how it represents historical time through historical writing.

However, how are these operations eventually carried out?

On the one hand, for Koselleck, time is a metahistorical category that “is embedded in every experience of history, which implies the basic distinction between present, past, and future” (BOUTON, 2016BOUTON, Christophe. The Critical Theory of History: Rethinking the Philosophy of History in the Light of Koselleck’s Work. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 2, n. 55, p. 163-184, 2016, 163-184, 2016, https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668 , 29/04/2022.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668...
, p. 180). On the other hand, the experience of historical time is the lived, “existential time” (BOUTON, 2016BOUTON, Christophe. The Critical Theory of History: Rethinking the Philosophy of History in the Light of Koselleck’s Work. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 2, n. 55, p. 163-184, 2016, 163-184, 2016, https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668 , 29/04/2022.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668...
, p. 180). According to Olsen, it is difficult to separate Koselleck’s theory of time (historical ontology) from the Koselleckian approach to the experience of historical time (historical epistemology) since he has never explicitly connected them (OLSEN, 2013OLSEN, Niklas. History in the Plural: An introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck. New York: Berghahn Books, 2013. , p. 230-231). These two dimensions are indeed “hard to reconcile” (ANKERSMIT, 2021, p. 40) Despite that restriction, according to Jordheim, some links between both are made throughout his works (JORDHEIM, 2011JORDHEIM, Helge. Does Conceptual History Really Need a Theory of Historical Times? Contributions to the History of Concepts, Oxford, v. 6, n. 2, p. 21-41, 2011, 21-41, 2011, https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202 , 24/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202...
, p. 22-23). The interplay between the metahistoricity of the historical ontology and the varieties of historical experience that the historical epistemology approaches is prone to be explained as we assume with Hellerma that the “relationship between the two frameworks [should be interpreted] not necessarily in terms of opposition and exclusion, but rather as complementary” (HELLERMA, 2020bHELLERMA, Juhan. Koselleck on Modernity, Historik, and Layers of Time. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 59, n. 2, p. 188-209, 2020b, 188-209, 2020b, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154 , 23/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154...
, p. 189).

For the Koselleckian quasi-substantive temporalization to be fully accomplished by the combination between the metaphysics of historical time and the experienced historical time, two concomitant movements shall be discriminated. On the one side, (t.1) the experienced historical time embodies the quasi-substantive temporalization insofar as the temporal structure is periodized according to regimes of historicity. On the other side, (t.2) the experienced historical time retemporalizes the quasi-substantive temporalization by means of the flexibilization of the historical structure of time. The combination of operations t.1 and t.2 performs the historically-experienced temporalization and gives access to the temporalization that the historical writing provides regarding the historiographical regimes. Hence, we will proceed by detailing the demarches that t.1 and t.2 imply.

(t.1.1) Firstly, for Koselleck, the structure of historical time can be historically analyzed by the differential relations between “space of experience” and the “horizon of expectation” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 263). The distance between these temporal markers changes the perception of the relationship among past, present, and future so that the quasi-substantive structure of historical time is specified according to different historical experiences. Those temporal markers perform the Koselleckian historically-experienced temporalization as they ascribe an intrinsic periodization to the quasi-substantive temporalization by differentiating kinds of historical experience over time.

(t.1.2) Secondly, the temporal structure specifies different, but not randomly, experienced structures of historical time according to a major guiding vector, “The technology-induced acceleration of temporal rhythms” (EWING, 2016EWING, Alexander B. Conceptions of Reinhart Koselleck’s Theory of Historical Time in the Thinking of Michael Oakeshott. History of European Ideas, s/l, v. 42, n. 3, p. 412-129, 2016, 412-129, 2016, https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2015.1118331 , 20/04/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2015.11...
, p. 420), which speeds up over time. Therefore, the multilayeredness that characterizes the structure of historical time contracts and protracts at different paces. If a change takes longer, the present becomes closer to the past; therefore, history is experienced as a repetition of the past. Otherwise, if temporal changes come along frequently, the present circumscribes to an episodic timeline, so that the past recedes as a detached dimension and history is experienced disruptively regarding past experiences. Thus, the Koselleckian quasi-substantive temporalization is measured according to the periodization of different rhythms related to the experienced historical time.

(t.1.3) Thirdly, the periodization of the temporal structure of history becomes historiographically intelligible through the semantic shift of the concepts that are used to refer to the historical experience, so that different temporal experiences become immanently perceptible in the “linguistic organization of temporal experience” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 4). A shorter distance between the space of experience and the horizon of expectation characterizes the past-dominant Historia Magistra Vitae (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 28), and a wider distance characterizes the future-dominant historical experience of modernity, the Neuzeit (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 225-263). The shifts between the latter and the former taking place around 1780 can be observed in the historiographical vocabulary. As the Historia Magistra Vitae and the Neuzeit involve the experienced historical time, they can be properly named regimes of hostoricity after Hartog’s categorization, even though Koselleck uses the expression “regimes of temporality” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. xvi) to name the pattern-like, metahistorical, though transitory, structures of repetition in history.

On the one side, the experienced historical time immanently discriminates the quasi-substantive temporalization according to different periods. Reciprocally, on the other side, for the Koselleckian temporalizations of multiple temporalities to be complete, the quasi-substantive historical temporalization should be internally affected or retemporalized (t.2). The operation of retemporalizing the quasi-substantive temporalization accomplishes the Koselleckian historically-experienced temporalization by means of two interconnected operations.

(t.2.1) Firstly, the quasi-substantive temporalization and the historical experience superimpose one another due to the structural game they play, describing different ways that the relationship among past, present, and future (regimes of historicity) might take. In fact, the Koselleckian semantics of historical time shows that the relationship between the experience and the structure of historical time historically changes, not only in terms of the experienced historical time, but also according to the order of the temporal structure that underlies the regimes of historicity. This changeable characteristic of the Koselleckian structure of historical time is the main character regarding the characterization of the quasi-substantive temporalization.

To be precise, the historical experience of past societies (Historia Magistra Vitae) before modernity found temporal references outside the historical events that instantiated those experiences. The historical events were scanned and ordered upon natural scales and theological plots. As the space of experience was closer, according to to the Historia Magister Vitae regime of historicity, the past was projected into the horizon of expectation as a changeless historical experience whose structure of repetition demands natural or messianic temporal markers. In contrast, the modern experience of historical time, represented by the Neuzeit, owing to a wider distance between past and future, and the acceleration of time imposed by technology, required the experience of historical time to be referenced by the historical events themselves, so that “chronology [started to] be arranged according to history and not history according to chronology” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 106) and “Time becomes a dynamic and historical force in its own right” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 236).

The acceleration of time, therefore, owes its formal conditions to the temporal layers that dislocate the tensions and the relative acceleration between past and present regarding on how fast they slow down or speed up (HELLERMA, 2020bHELLERMA, Juhan. Koselleck on Modernity, Historik, and Layers of Time. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 59, n. 2, p. 188-209, 2020b, 188-209, 2020b, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154 , 23/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154...
, p. 188-189; 202-203). As the modern temporality speeds the rate of temporal change, history became the driving force of transformation within time, and the “coefficients of motion and acceleration which are no longer derivative of expectations of the Last Judgment […] remain [instead] adequate to […] a world increasingly technical in nature.” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 104). Consequently, the space of experience could not find its smooth and expected continuity in the distant horizon of expectation, in as much as historical change “occurs at increasingly shorter intervals of time” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 314), “because the structural preconditions are themselves changing more quickly than had been previously possible” (KOSELLECK, 2018KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018., p. 265).

In this sense, the temporalization of the quasi-substantive has an internal effect upon the structure of time itself. We call this operation retemporalization of the temporal structure by historical experience.

(t.2.2) Secondly, and consequently, the historically determined regimes of historicity, as past and future increasingly move away from each other according to the space of experience and horizon of expectation, present the case study whereupon the experienced historical time determines the quasi-substantive temporalization. In fact, in the modern regime of temporality, the experienced historical time allows the structure of temporality to reveal its historically-determinate characteristic. It means that the short-circuit that the structure of historical time undergoes as the modern experience of historical time arose (Sattelzeit) provides a heuristic tool for theorists to deal with and scrutinize regimes of historicity and for historians to disentangle the historiographical regimes (narratives) from the perspective of our modern historical experience. The current historical point of view can observe itself in its relative and ephemeral position: “the question of temporal structure […] discloses a means of adequately examining the whole domain of historical investigation, without being limited by the […] semantic threshold for our [from around 1780] experience” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 94). Thus, the retemporalization of the quasi-substantive of Koselleck’s historical ontology assigns an epistemological consequence for the historians’ disciplinary task.

The new metaphysicians of time do not frustrate the relationship between the theories of time and the historiographical regimes of historical writing either. As already stated by Hartog, the regimes of historicity set “the conditions of possibility of historical writing” (HARTOG, 2015HARTOG, François. Regimes of Historicity: Presentism and Experiences of Time. Translated by Saskya Brown. New York: Columbia University Press , 2015., p. 17). Plus, according to Mudrovcic “there should be a change in the perception of time that historiography portrays whenever the way a society, the western one in this case, articulates past, present, changes” (MUDROVCIC, 2019MUDROVCIC, María Inés. Experimentar el Tiempo, Escribir la Historia. In: ARAVENA, Pablo (ed.). Representación histórica y nueva experiencia del tempo. Valparaíso: Editorial América en Movimiento, 2019. p. 23-35. , p. 23). Koselleck, as early as 1970, in a conference paper stated that not only regimes of historicity but also temporal structures organize both “historical writing” and “history itself” (OLSEN, 2013OLSEN, Niklas. History in the Plural: An introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck. New York: Berghahn Books, 2013. , p. 219).

For instance, the historical writing of the “Christian experience of history” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 29; 229-230), which belonged to the Historia Magister Vitae, according to Koselleck, provided the narrative coherence of “world history” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. p. 35; 230-231) by the end of the eighteenth century, when the modern experience of time arouse. The Historia Magister Vitae, though past-centered and cosmologically referenced ancient historical experience, allowed the historical writing to redirect the narrative from the exemplary past to engage historians with the anticipation of the future according to the historically temporalized modern historical experience (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 40-41; 234-236).

Final Remarks

Our main goal was to characterize the epistemic unity of the new metaphysics of historical time as it emerges and develops in the recent theory of history. According to this goal, different varieties of temporalization related to history as a discipline were categorized, namely: the chronological-historical, the substantive, the quasi-substantive, and the historically-experienced temporalization. This categorial framework intends to cover many a theory of time (theories of presence, theories of multitemporalities, analytical theories about historical time). The theories of the new metaphysics of historical time should combine these different temporalizations to be competitive in the new disciplinary field.

This main goal forked in two specific goals. Firstly, the effort of categorizing varieties of temporalization aimed at characterizing the emergent field of the new metaphysics of time in order to establish its boundaries and to understand its many conceptual achievements from a standpoint that reveals the epistemic unity of the recent time studies. Secondly, this article reveals the conceptual work about time that runs unnoticed beneath the historian’s disciplinary tasks. To that effect, Koselleck’s concepts related to natural and historical time were taken as examples of the new metaphysics of time as it combines different varieties of temporalization.

The temporal structure upon which the Koselleckian theory of time lies temporalizes natural time by including the bold natural repetition as nature-like patterns of repetition in history. According to this operation, the temporalization considers natural time as one of its factors. As seen, the overlapping between the modern historical experience of time (Neuzeit) and the temporal structure of history performs this phenomenon insofar as history started to be temporalized by human events in the turning of the eighteenth to the nineteenth century. As a matter of fact, the “temporalization of history” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 37) corresponds with the reverse phenomenon of the “denaturalization of historical temporalities” (KOSELLECK, 2004KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. , p. 104; 113) as natural scales and theological plots were no longer used to measure history.

Nevertheless, technical progress increasingly thrusted historical time into natural time to the extent that it started a historicization of natural time, reversing the former modernist tendency of denaturalization of historical time. Nowadays, a counterpoint to the phenomenon that Koselleck called “temporalization of history” arises. In contrast, recent reflections about future scenarios beyond the human era, in special those that Posthumanism and Anthropocene provide, prospect “the definitive re-entry of the natural world into the time of human life” (LOPES; VIANA JUNIOR, 2020LOPES, Alfredo R. S.; VIANA JUNIOR, Mário M. O Antropoceno como Regime de Historicidade [The Anthropocene as a Regime of Historicity] , Revista Brasileira de História & Ciências Sociais, Porto Alegre, v. 12, n. 23, p. 9-24, 2020, 9-24, 2020, https://doi.org/10.14295/rbhcs.v12i23.11708 , 03/10/2022.
https://doi.org/10.14295/rbhcs.v12i23.11...
, p. 22). Therefore, they require historians to understand and to explain that the intertwined natural and historical time includes the “changes in the entangled human/nonhuman world” (SIMON, 2019cSIMON, Zóltan B. The Transformation of Historical Time: Processual and Evental Temporalities. In: TAMM, M.; OLIVIER, Laurent (ed.). Rethinking Historical Time: New Approaches to Presentism. London/New York: Bloomsbury Publishing, 2019c. p. 71-84., p. 80). It means that a renaturalization of historical time is under way (JORDHEIM, 2022JORDHEIM, Helge. Natural Histories for The Anthropocene: Koselleck’s Theories and The Possibility of a History of Lifetimes. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 61, n. 3, p. 391-425, 2022, 391-425, 2022, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268 , 30/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268...
, p. 413-415) provided that from inside history historians have been urged by natural forces to look upon ourselves from the outside.

This phenomenon does not concern historians only, since “more and more non-historians award an unprecedentedly central place to the historicity of the physical and living world” (QUENET, 2017QUENET, Grégory. The Anthropocene and the Time of Historians. Translated from French by Katharine Throssell. Annales: Histoire, Sciences Sociales, Paris, v. 72, n. 2, p. 267-299, 2017, 267-299, 2017, https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-2017-2-page-267.htm , 23/09/2022.
https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-201...
, p. 196). And this is a challenge that the categorial framework launched in this article must face. It remains to be inspected if new quasi-substantive varieties of temporalization arise when human time does not rule alone historiographical work. Provided that historians must deal with time scales that are non-synchronous, or even desynchronous, with historical time, they are challenged “to make visible the alternative temporalizations and historicizations” (JORDHEIM, 2022JORDHEIM, Helge. Natural Histories for The Anthropocene: Koselleck’s Theories and The Possibility of a History of Lifetimes. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 61, n. 3, p. 391-425, 2022, 391-425, 2022, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268 , 30/03/2023.
https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268...
, p. 395), which might reintegrate the plurality of historical times in the plurality of natural times.

REFERENCES

  • BEVERNAGE, Berber; ALMEIDA, Gisele I. de; DELANOTE, Broos; FROEYMAN, Anton; HUIJBERS, Patty; MIEROOP, Kenan Van de. Philosophy of History after 1945: a bibliometric study. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 53, n. 3, p. 406-436, 2019, 406-436, 2019, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12124 , 03/03/2023.
    » https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12124
  • BLOCH, Marc. The Historian’s Craft. New York: Vintage Books, 1953.
  • BOCCARDI, Emiliano. Recent Trends in the Philosophy of Time: An Introduction to Time and Reality I. Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 39, n. 4, p. 5-34, 2016.
  • BRAUDEL, Fernand. On History. Translated by Sarah Matthews. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1982.
  • BOUTON, Christophe. The Critical Theory of History: Rethinking the Philosophy of History in the Light of Koselleck’s Work. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 2, n. 55, p. 163-184, 2016, 163-184, 2016, https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668 , 29/04/2022.
    » https://www.jstor.org/stable/24809668
  • DANTO, Arthur C. Narration and knowledge. New York: Columbia University Press, 1985.
  • DELEUZE, Gilles. Masochism: coldness and cruelty & Venus in Furs. New York: Zone Books, 1991.
  • DENG, Natalja. Metaphysics of time. In: CRANE, Tim (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 2018.
  • DUMMETT, Michael. Metaphysics of Time. In: DUMMETT, Michael (ed.). Truth and the Past. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004. p. 73-96.
  • ESCUDIER, Alexandre. “Temporalization” and Political Modernity: thinking with Koselleck. Annales: Histoire, Sciences Sociales, Paris, v. 64, n. 6, p. 1269-1301, 2009, 1269-1301, 2009, https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-2009-6-page-1269.htm , 23/09/2022.
    » https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-2009-6-page-1269.htm
  • ESPOSITO, Fernando. Despite Singularity: The Event and its Manifold Structures of Repetition. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 60, n. 1, p. 86-101, 2021, 86-101, 2021, http://www.jstor.org/stable/27799186 , 31/03/2023.
    » http://www.jstor.org/stable/27799186
  • EWING, Alexander B. Conceptions of Reinhart Koselleck’s Theory of Historical Time in the Thinking of Michael Oakeshott. History of European Ideas, s/l, v. 42, n. 3, p. 412-129, 2016, 412-129, 2016, https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2015.1118331 , 20/04/2023.
    » https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2015.1118331
  • GORMAN, Jonathan. The Limits of Historiographical Choice in Temporal Distinctions. In: LOREN, Chris; BERBER; Bevernage (ed.). Breaking up Time: Negotiating the Borders between Present, Past and Future. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2013. p. 155-175.
  • GRUBER, R. P.; BLOCK, R. A.; MONTEMAYOR C, -. Physical Time Within Human Time. Frontiers in Psychology, s/l, v. 13, article n. 718505, p. 1-13, 2022, 1-13, 2022, https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.718505 , 25/03/2023.
    » https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.718505
  • HAROOTUNIAN, Harry. Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts: Hayden White and the Question of Temporal Form. In: DORAN, Robert (ed.). Philosophy of History After Hayden White. London: Bloomsbury, 2013. p. 119-149.
  • HARTOG, François; LENCLUD, Gérard. Régimes d’historicité. In: DUTU, Alexandre; DODILLE, Norbert (ed.). L´état des lieux en sciences sociales. Paris: L’Hamartan, 1993. p. 26-27.
  • HARTOG, François. Regimes of Historicity: Presentism and Experiences of Time. Translated by Saskya Brown. New York: Columbia University Press , 2015.
  • HELLERMA, Juhan. Mapping Time: Analysis of Contemporary Theories of Historical Temporality. Tartu: University of Tartu Press, 2020a.
  • HELLERMA, Juhan. Koselleck on Modernity, Historik, and Layers of Time. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 59, n. 2, p. 188-209, 2020b, 188-209, 2020b, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154 , 23/03/2023.
    » https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12154
  • HUNT, Lynn Avery. Measuring Time, Making History. Budapest: Central European University Share Company, 2008. p. 144-159.
  • IGGERS, George G. Introduction. In: IGGERS, Georg G (ed.). The Theory and Practice of History: Leopold von Ranke. London: Routledge , 2011. p. xi-xlv.
  • ISMAEL, Jenann. From Physical Time to Human Time. In: DOLEV, Yuval; ROUBACH, Michael (ed.). Cosmological and Psychological Time. London: Springer. 2016. p. 107-124.
  • JORDHEIM, Helge. Does Conceptual History Really Need a Theory of Historical Times? Contributions to the History of Concepts, Oxford, v. 6, n. 2, p. 21-41, 2011, 21-41, 2011, https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202 , 24/03/2023.
    » https://doi.org/10.3167/choc.2011.060202
  • JORDHEIM, Helge. Natural Histories for The Anthropocene: Koselleck’s Theories and The Possibility of a History of Lifetimes. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 61, n. 3, p. 391-425, 2022, 391-425, 2022, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268 , 30/03/2023.
    » https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12268
  • KING, Preston. Thinking Past a Problem: Essays on the History of Ideas. London: Frank Cass, 2000.
  • KLEINBERG, Ethan. Introduction: The New Metaphysics of Time. History and Theory, Virtual Issue, Middletown, p. 1-7, 2012, 1EthanIntro-1509464921000.pdf (wiley.com) , 26/03/2019.
  • KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Translated by Keith Tribe. New York: Columbia University Press , 2004.
  • KOSELLECK, Reinhart. Sediments Of Time: On Possible Histories. Translated by Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2018.
  • KOSELLECK, Reinhart. The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Translated by Todd Samuel, Kirstin Behnke and Jobst Welge. Stanford: Stanford University Press , 2002.
  • KOSELLECK, Reinhart. “ Über die Theoriebedürftigkeit der Geschichtswissenschaft ”. In: KOSELLECK, Reinhart; GADAMER, Hans-Georg. Zeitschichten: Studien zur Historik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2000. p. 298-316
  • LE GOFF, Jacques. Histoire et mémoire. Paris: Gallimard, 1988.
  • LOPES, Alfredo R. S.; VIANA JUNIOR, Mário M. O Antropoceno como Regime de Historicidade [The Anthropocene as a Regime of Historicity] , Revista Brasileira de História & Ciências Sociais, Porto Alegre, v. 12, n. 23, p. 9-24, 2020, 9-24, 2020, https://doi.org/10.14295/rbhcs.v12i23.11708 , 03/10/2022.
    » https://doi.org/10.14295/rbhcs.v12i23.11708
  • LORENZ, Chris. History and Theory. In: SCHNEIDER, Axel; WOOLF, Daniel (ed.). The Oxford History of Historical Writing: Historical Writing Since 1945, v. 5. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. p. 13-35.
  • LORENZ, Chris. The Times They are a-Changin on Time, Space and Periodization in History. In: CARRETERO, Mario; BERGER, Stefan Berger; GREVER, Maria Grever (ed.). Palgrave Handbook of Research in Historical Culture and Education. Londres: Palgrave Macmillan, 2017. p. 109-131.
  • MEYER, Ulrich. Consciousness and the Present. In: DOLEV, Yuval; ROUBACH, Michael (ed.). Cosmological and Psychological Time. New York: Springer, 2016. p. 143-153.
  • MUDROVCIC, María Inés. Experimentar el Tiempo, Escribir la Historia. In: ARAVENA, Pablo (ed.). Representación histórica y nueva experiencia del tempo. Valparaíso: Editorial América en Movimiento, 2019. p. 23-35.
  • OLSEN, Niklas. History in the Plural: An introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck. New York: Berghahn Books, 2013.
  • OAKLANDER, Nathan L. Debates in the Metaphysics of Time, New York/London: Bloomsbury , 2014.
  • POMIAN, Krzysztof. L’Ordre du temps. Paris: Gallimard , 1984.
  • QUENET, Grégory. The Anthropocene and the Time of Historians. Translated from French by Katharine Throssell. Annales: Histoire, Sciences Sociales, Paris, v. 72, n. 2, p. 267-299, 2017, 267-299, 2017, https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-2017-2-page-267.htm , 23/09/2022.
    » https://www.cairn.info/revue-annales-2017-2-page-267.htm
  • RICOEUR, Paul. Memory, history, forgetting. Translated by Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004.
  • RUNIA, Eelco. “Presence”, History and Theory, Middletown, v. 45, n. 1, p. 1-29, 2006, 1-29, 2006, https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590722 , 15/02/2019.
    » https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590722
  • RUSEN, Jorn. Historik: Theorie der Geschichtswissenschaft. Kol/Weimar/Wein: Bohlau Verlag, 2013.
  • SIMON, Zoltán Boldizsár. The story of humanity and the challenge of posthumanity. History of the Human Sciences, s/l, v. 2, n. 32, p. 101-120, 2019a, 101-120, 2019a, https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695118779519 , 14/02/2022.
    » https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695118779519
  • SIMON, Zóltan B. History in Times of Unprecedented Change: A Theory for the 21st Century. London: Bloomsbury , 2019b.
  • SIMON, Zóltan B. The Transformation of Historical Time: Processual and Evental Temporalities. In: TAMM, M.; OLIVIER, Laurent (ed.). Rethinking Historical Time: New Approaches to Presentism. London/New York: Bloomsbury Publishing, 2019c. p. 71-84.
  • WHITE, Hayden. Metahistory: the historical imagination in nineteenth-century Europe. Maryland: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975.
  • ZAMMITO, John. Historians and Philosophy of Historiography. In: TUCKER, Aviezer (ed.). A Companion to Philosophy of History and Historiography. Oxford: Blackwell, 2009. p. 63-84.
  • ZAMMITO, John. Koselleck’s Philosophy of Historical Time(s) and the Practice of History. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 43, n. 1, p. 124-135, 2004, 124-135, 2004, https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590747 , 20/04/2023.
    » https://www.jstor.org/stable/3590747
  • ZAMMITO, John. Koselleck’s Times. History and Theory, Middletown, v. 60, n. 2, p. 396-405, 2021, https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12215, 21/03/2023
    » https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12215, 21/03/2023
  • 1
    In the jargon of the metaphysics of time, this integration corresponds with the conciliation between A-theory and B-theory, which McTaggart, the founder of the metaphysics of time, considered thoroughly incompatible.

Additional Information

  • Funding

    Not applicable.
  • Ethics Committee Approval

    Not applicable.
  • Research Context

    This article composes an integrated ambience of research with two research projects granted by the National Council for Scientific and Technological Development (CNPq), Brazil, “A Transitional Scenario of the Theory of History: ‘Post-Narrativism’ and New Concepts of Historical Time” e “A Transitional Scenario of the Theory and Philosophy of History: Mapping the “New Metaphysics of Time” (CNPQ registration nº 303415/2019-3). It is also supported by the Research Group registered at CNPQ: Historical Temporalities: metaphysics of historical time, regimes of historicity, historiographical regimes, historical-natural time (Anthropocene, Post-Human)
  • Evaluation Method

    Double-Blind Peer Review.
  • Availability of research data and other materials

    Not applicable.

Edited by

Editors

Flávia Varella - Editor-in-chief Fábio Duarte Joly- Executive editor

Data availability

Not applicable.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    13 May 2024
  • Date of issue
    2023

History

  • Received
    04 Oct 2022
  • Reviewed
    25 Jan 2023
  • Accepted
    03 Apr 2023
Sociedade Brasileira de Teoria e História da Historiografia (SBTHH) Rua do Seminário, s/n, Centro. , CEP: 35420-000, Tel: +55 (31) 3557 9423 - Mariana - MG - Brazil
E-mail: sbthh@yahoo.com.br